miércoles, 26 de febrero de 2020

George Dickie (1984). 'The Art Circle: A Theory of Art.'


George Dickie.
The Art Circle: A Theory of Art.
Chicago Spectrum Press, 1997.
(1st ed.: New York, New Haven Publications, 1984.)

I) THE PHILOSOPHY OF ART

In philosophy, the theory of art as imitation goes back to Plato. It extended for more than two millennia.

Then, the so-called «expression theory of art» was born in the 19th century. It was the «first theory to challenge the imitation theory». [Two instances of «expressivistic» philosophers are Benedetto Croce and R. G. Collingwood.1] To understand better the expression theory, I [ICS] quote Martin L. Shough:
«a) the composer’s experience gives rise to ‘states of mind,’
»b) these states are codified as pieces of music,
»c) the music is in turn decoded by a listener into an emulation or understanding of that state of mind.»2

[I distinguish in Slough’s words the notion of the listener of music as a sort of «gramophone». According to this, we only try to recreate what the composer originally felt; and, if we deviate from that, we lapse into a mistaken interpretation of the work. This can be extended to all consumers of any work of art.]

After the avant-garde movements of the 20th century, a third theory emerged: the so-called «Real Theory of Art». «Art, the new theory says, is the creation of forms which are not imitations.» (18.) Thus [I say, ICS], a Cubist still life, or Piet Mondrian’s Tableau I of 1921, or Barnett Newman’s Onement I of 1948, to mention only three instances, are neither optical imitations of the external aspect of objects nor manifestations of «states of mind» in the expressivistic sense.

[The imitation theory and the expression theory had many followers among theoreticians. The «real theory» was fitting for all Cubist-derived and abstract artists. Surely there were more new theories in the 20th century, but they are not present in this text because of lack of space.]

Then came the «institutional theory of art». The inspiration for it was Arthur Danto’s article “The Artworld” (1964). «By an institutional approach I mean the idea that works of art are art as a result of the position they occupy within an institutional framework or context. The institutional theory is, then, a kind of contextual theory.» (7.)

Dickie doesn’t take art as a synonym of «something valuable» or «masterpiece». «… the theory of art is about a value-neutral, classificatory sense of “work of art.”» (13.) «… artmaking is something which almost everyone can do. It is not a highly specialized activity […] masterpieces constitute only a minute part» of art. (14.)


II) DANTO AND THE REVIVAL OF THEORY

In «The Artworld,» Danto argues that what makes art possible are artistic theories. Dickie offers one possible interpretation of this: artistic theories are just any «ideas either explicitly or implicitly about what counts as art.» «In this weak sense, everyone would have a theory about almost everything that he did…» (20.) Nevertheless, after «The Artworld,» Danto does not raise that notion again.

Dickie counters Danto: «…to conclude that two things (in this case art and the philosophy of art) are identical because they share a characteristic (in this case have art as subject) is to commit the fallacy of undistributed middle term.» (23.) [The fallacy goes like this: «All Z is B. All Y is B. Therefore, all Y is Z.»] «…in the end we have the case of a philosopher trying to dictate to artists.» (24.)

In a second article, «Artworks and Real Things» (1973), Danto «may be suggesting a sufficient condition of art: 1) if something is [...] a statement [...] then that is a sufficient condition for that thing to be an artwork. […] 2) in order for something to be an artwork, it is necessary for that thing to be at some remove from reality (and being a statement is one way of being at some remove from reality […]).» (21-22.) In that sense, «a fake does not make a statement, it only pretends to.» (22.)

Can chimpanzees make art? Danto and Dickie deny it. «Chimpanzees can neither grasp the institutional framework of artworks (my view) nor make objects which are about something (Danto’s view).» But can children make art? Danto answers: no. But Dickie says: yes. Children’s work can be accommodated within Dickie’s institutional theory – kids do have a general idea of artmaking.

There is a third article by Danto, «The Transfiguration of the Commonplace» (1974). There, «Danto maintains that aboutness is a necessary condition for artworks; that is, he contends that a semantic dimension is required for being a work of art.» (10.) According to this idea of Danto, «artworks are about something.» (23.) «By contrast, the institutional view as I have conceived it […] does not necessarily involve the category of language» (10) or language’s representative function. Therefore, art for Dickie is not necessarily «a statement (or being about something)» (26.) For instance, «it does not seem possible that the great bulk of music could be shown to have a semantic dimension.» (24.) «So aboutness cannot be a necessary condition of art. I conclude that Danto’s claim about art is false.» (25.)


III) ART AS ARTIFICE

In the 1950s there was a so-called «new conception of art», headed by Morris Weitz and Paul Ziff.3 For Weitz, the concept of art is a class of objects. This class «may be enlarged at any time» and is defined according to two criteria:

1) similarity, «resembling a prior-established work of art»; in turn, «Ziff remarks that “No rules can be given to determine what is or is not a sufficient degree of similarity”» (33); and

2) «calling something art.» (31.)

Weitz thinks that «“work of art” cannot be defined because the class of works of art is one whose members have no common feature.» Weitz’s view of the term «work of art» is senseless, as Dickie expresses. Weitz’s and Ziff’s conception is, then, radically open [ICS].

The «new conception of art» is a double theory, because it is based on 1) similarity, and 2) the work being an artifact. This «subclass of artifactual art (nonsimilarity art) […] is the old familiar class of paintings, poems, musical pieces, and the like, which are crafted in various traditional ways.» (35.) Similarity does not necessarily imply traditional craftsmanship (artifactuality) and vice versa.

Even so, «The first question with which philosophers of art must deal is “What are the limits of making?” not “What are the limits of the use of art and work of art?” or “What are the limits of similarity?”» (37.)

For Dickie, «an artifact need not be a physical object» but is always man-made. This applies even to the case of picking a given object: «suppose a piece of driftwood is picked up by someone who is familiar with the world of art and taken home and hung on a wall, unaltered […] The driftwood is being used as an artistic medium and being displayed within the context of the artworld, and it thereby becomes part of a more complex object [...] the-driftwood-used-as-an-artistic-medium [...]» (45.) This is a way of achieving (not conferring) artifactuality. «The urinal Duchamp used to make Fountain is like the driftwood used as an artifact medium; it became an artifact of an artworld system.» (46.)

When is artifactuality not achieved? By “pointing and calling”, like «Dali’s alleged claim that some rocks were art because he had pointed at them and said they were art.» (46.) [This is the same as Robert Barry’s conceptual pieces.] [I disagree with Dickie. There is intellectual work behind the pointing and calling. ICS.]


IV) THE INSTITUTIONAL NATURE OF ART

Dickie stresses that the institution mentioned in the institutional theory of art is not «a formally organized body» (9; bold italics mine). Instead, «art-making is an Action-institution and does not involve any Person-institution in any essential way.» (52.) This follows a concept given by Jeffrey Wieand:4 «Person-institutions are organizations which behave as quasi-persons or agents, as, for example, the Catholic Church and General Motors do» (52), whereas there are “institution-types”,5 such as «tool-making, storytelling, marriage, or the like,» which are more general. Art is as general as an Action-institution (Wieand) and an institution-type (Beardsley).

«Beardsley proposes as a contrast with the institutional conception of art and artists what he calls the “Romantic” conception of the artist—an artist working in producing art in isolation from any institutions. Of course, he does not think all artists work in such isolation …» (49.) Dickie puts forth: «Suppose that a person totally ignorant of the concept of art (the member of a primitive tribe or the culturally isolated individual mentioned above, for example) and unacquainted with any representations were to fashion a representation of something out of clay. […] the creator of the representation cannot recognize his creation as art and that therefore, it cannot be art. […] he lacks the relevant cognitive structures. Art cannot exist in the contextless vacuum that Beardsley’s view requires; it must exist in a cultural matrix, as the product of someone fulfilling a cultural role.» (55.)

«[...] an artist also creates for a public of some sort. […] Even art not intended for public presentation presupposes a public …» (65.) «I speak of a more or less prepared public because artists sometimes surprise their publics.» (66.) «[…] being a thing of a kind which is presented to an artworld public is a necessary condition for being a work of art. […] “Subject matter” frameworks of the kind envisioned by the imitation theory, Langer's theory, or even Danto’s “aboutness” theory are not, it is clear, viable frameworks.» (67.)

Dickie now approaches Timothy Binkley’s «institutional-like approach».6 «Simple specification occurred, according to Binkley, when Robert Barry made a work of art by saying (specifying) that it is “all the things I know but of which I am not at the moment thinking—1:36 P.M.; 15 June 1969, New York.” […] I believe that Binkley also thinks that simple specification was used when Duchamp made Fountain. […] Binkley claims to make everything in the universe art by simple specification, thereby eliminating the problem of keeping track of which things in the universe are and which are not art.» (59.)

«Binkley's argument for Barry’s Thoughts and its ilk being art, as we have seen, is that they are created by recognized artists, treated by critics as art, written about in art journals, and, finally, that they have developed out of a cultural tradition. Binkley is of course right when he says that a philosopher in constructing a philosophy of art should look to the actual practices of artists, the sayings of critics, and so on. It does not follow from this, however, that a philosopher must take seriously everything that the denizens of the artworld do …» (60.)

«…Binkley treats Duchamp’s Fountain and Barry’s “piece” as if they were exactly the same type. They are, however, quite different: Fountain, to begin with, is a work of visual art […] and Barry’s “piece” is not.» (60.) «Barry's “piece” […] has no medium; it was not crafted with anything, it was just specified. […] Fountain is thus not, as Binkley thinks, a case of conceptual art, and conceptual art is art made by simple specification. […]» (60.)

When someone states that he or she has accomplished an activity, is that statement enough to accomplish that activity? «Sometimes it is, as Austin has taught us» with the notion of performativity of language. (61.) But it doesn’t always happen. Art is a context where such an assertion is not enough. «Making art has had at its center working with a medium. […] It will not do, I think, to say that Barry’s unthought knowledge is his medium. Barry does not work his unthought knowledge nor does Binkley the universe, they just refer to these things in an unusual way.» [But referring is working them – thought is work! ICS.] (61.)

In spite of the above argued, it is inevitable that «Some will no doubt wish to claim that with Thoughts Barry is trying to extend and succeeds in extending the cultural tradition in somewhat the way it was expanded when another actor was added to the Greek drama or when artists began to use acrylic paints.» (61.)


V) THE ARTWORLD

It is an «obvious fact that creating art is an intentional activity […].» (71.) «The role of a member of the public also has two central aspects. First […] the awareness that what is presented to them is art. The second aspect […] is the wide variety of abilities and sensitivities which enables one to perceive and understand the particular kind of art with which one is presented.» (72.)

«…the artworld consists of a set of individual artworld systems, each of which contains its own specific artist roles plus specific supplementary roles. For example, painting is one artworld system, theater is another, and so on.» (75.)

We finally arrive at George Dickie’s Criteria about art:

«I) An artist is a person who participates with understanding in the making of a work of art. […]
«II) A work of art is an artifact of a kind created to be presented to an artworld public. […]
«III) A public is a set of persons the members of which are prepared in some degree to understand an object which is presented to them. […]
«IV) The artworld is the totality of all artworld systems. [...]
«V) An artworld system is a framework for the presentation of a work of art by an artist to an artworld public.» (80-82.)

This takes us to the conclusion that «not everything can become a work of art.» Rather, «it is the work done in creating an object against the background of the artworld which establishes that object as a work of art.» (12.)

«Some may feel these results involve a vicious circularity» (77), but, nevertheless, «if art is the sort of thing I think it is, the only correct account of it would have to be a circular account.» (78.) «Artist, work of art, artworld, and artworld system are what I shall call “inflected concepts.” […] a set of concepts which bend in on themselves, presupposing and supporting one another. No member of such a set can be understood apart from all the other concepts in the set.» (84.)

«There are basic or primitive terms which are unanalyzable and, hence, undefinable.» (77.) It is useless to learn about them through «the theories or definitions of philosophers […].» (83.) Rather, we «learn the meaning of these primitive terms only in some nonlinguistic way: sensory experience, rational intuition, or whatever.» (77.) That is the case of the term «art.» «We learn about art in different ways, but we invariably do so at a tender age.» (83.) «Virtually everyone, including even quite small children, has at least a partial understanding of the expression “work of art.”» In practical terms, «virtually no one is in need of a definition of “work of art”» in the same way as when we find «an unfamiliar word.» (79.)

«The institutional theory, however, places virtually no restrictions on what art may do […] The institutional nature of art does not prevent art from serving moral, political, romantic, expressive, aesthetic, or a host of other needs.» (86.)


VI) AESTHETIC OBJECT

Dickie accepts «Monroe Beardsley’s meaning of “aesthetic object of a work of art,” namely, “those properties of a work of art which are properly appreciated and/or criticized.”»7 (89.) «The first attack on the institutional theory of aesthetic object which I will consider is that of Robert Schultz.»8 (91.)

According to Schultz —and Dickie accepts this— there must be a «distinction between an independent sense of the aesthetic and a dependent sense of the aesthetic. The independent sense […] has no necessary connection to art.» (91.) «Schultz’s argument runs as follows:

»[…] 2) “…appreciation [of the mere visual sensations] is irrelevant to the proper treatment of Duchamp’s urinal as an art object.”
»[…] 5) […] “…Dickie’s account makes it fundamentally arbitrary … just which … objects are art objects.”
»[…] conclusion: it is an absurd result that “…Sophocles’ Oedipus Rex, a 200-year-old pine tree, Goedel’s Theorem, and an act of kindness …” can all be works of art.» (92.)

But Schultz «fails to take account of the context in which candidacy for appreciation is embedded.» Appreciation must be a dependent sense of the aesthetic. (94.)

Dickie now addresses Gary Iseminger’s ideas.9 «Iseminger [...] agrees with me that not every property of a work of art is aesthetically relevant; or, in my terminology, not every property of a work of art is an element of the aesthetic object of that work. […] however, he says […] that there are “…aesthetically relevant properties of things which are not works of art,” and he gives as an example the delicacy of a flower.» (95.)

His problem is that «he is confusing the aesthetically relevant (that which belongs to the aesthetic object of a work of art) with aesthetic qualities or properties of the Sibley kind [i. e., the physical and merely perceptible ones; Kantian?]. […] aesthetic relevance cannot exist independently of art.» (96.)

«Iseminger’s account of aesthetic objects of works of art has essentially the same kind of flaw as Beardsley's account. What can be appreciated (for Beardsley it was what can we perceived) is not powerful enough to separate the aesthetically relevant properties of art from the aesthetically irrelevant properties of art […] The theories of both Beardsley and Iseminger fail because neither takes into account the fact that works of art are cultural objects which are created within complex artworld practices. They both treat works of art as if they were natural objects such as orange trees and sunsets.» (98.)

Robert McGregor and Carolyn Korsmeyer are two thinkers with whom Dickie now deals.10 They are interested only in the aesthetic qualities of art, not in the «“artistic” characteristics of art, i.e., those which are not linked to “aesthetic perception.”» Korsmeyer «gives a definition […] For her, “aesthetic qualities must mean those which can be appreciated without regard for practical, moral, or theoretical relevance.”» (102.) She and McGregor admit, nevertheless, that this doesn't help much «in resolving the problem of aesthetic relevance». (103.) As a matter of fact, «no one, including the aesthetic-attitude theorists, has succeeded in working out a theory which underlies the distinction between aesthetic qualities and nonaesthetic qualities.» (104.)

Dickie now recognizes two different senses of the word «aesthetic»: «a sense which refers to aesthetic qualities and a sense which refers to [...] all the properties of a work [of art] which are properly appreciated and/or criticized». This latter sense includes «various aesthetic qualities, nonaesthetic qualities, personal qualities, expressive qualities, representational characteristics, moral characteristics, and so on.» (105.) In fact, «the two senses have little or nothing in common.» (105.)

Although several authors, like Beardsley, Iseminger, and Jerome Stolnitz, put forth that there is «some general, clear-cut way» to distinguish aesthetic relevance (105), Dickie believes that the solution «will have to be a piecemeal affair …» (106.)

«As long as one is faced with traditional kinds of art, one can rely on the established conventions for guidance. When innovation occurs, one will be to a certain extent on one’s own to figure out what is going on, although since the innovation will occur within some traditional form or other, there will be some minimum of guidance.» (106.)


EPILOGUE: REFLECTIONS ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF ART

«…the institutional theory easily accommodates the representative, expressive, symbolic, formal, and such properties of art, but it rejects them as defining characteristics. There is nothing about the institutional theory which inhibits or restricts art in any way. Art has been the bearer of a myriad of things …» (110.)

«We have seen, however, that works of art do share properties—artifactuality and being of a kind created to be presented to an artworld public—and that these properties are sufficient for defining “art.” Are these properties the essence of art? […] Perhaps they do constitute the essence of art, but the institutional theory makes no claim that they do. […] I spoke of the essential framework of art. In so speaking, I do not intend to make any claim about a timeless essence of art […] In the case of the institutional theory, the definition of “art” is not at all foundational. The definitions are, as I said, inflected—they mutually support one another. […] The content of the institutional theory and its central definitions are radically different from those of the traditional theories […].» (111.)

NOTAS

1 Croce wrote Estetica come scienza dell'espressione e linguistica generale (1902) and Breviario di estetica (1913). R. G. Collingwood wrote The Principles of Art (1938).

2 Martin L. Shough. Truant Boy: Art, Authenticity and Paul McCartney.

3 Morris Weitz, «The Role of Theory in Aesthetics», Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 15 (1956); also, in many other sources. / Paul Ziff, «The Task of Defining a Work of Art», Philosophical Review, 62 (1953).

4 Jeffrey Wieand, «Can There Be an Institutional Theory of Art?», Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 39 (1981).

5 As given by Monroe Beardsley in «Is Art Essentially Institutional?», a chapter in the book Culture and Art, Lars Aagaard-Mogensen, ed. (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey, 1976).

6 Timothy Binkley, «Deciding about Art», a chapter in the book Culture and Art, Lars Aagaard-Mogensen, ed. (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey, 1976).

7 As criticized by Frank Sibley in «Aesthetic Concepts», a chapter in a book edited by Joseph Margolis: Philosophy Looks at the Arts (New York, 1962).

8 Robert Schultz, «Does Aesthetics Have to Do Anything with Art?», The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Summer 1978.

9 Gary Iseminger, «Appreciation, the Artworld, and the Aesthetic», a chapter in the book Culture and Art, edited by Lars Aagaard-Mogensen (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey, 1976).

10 Robert McGregor, «Art and the Aesthetic», The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Summer 1974. Carolyn Korsmeyer, «On Distinguishing ‘Aesthetic’ from ‘Artistic», The Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1977.

domingo, 16 de febrero de 2020

Cadeneros

La policía del arte. Los cadeneros del arte. Los cancerberos del arte. El álbum de estampitas del arte. Los Linneo del arte: los taxónomos que apuntan clase, orden, suborden, familia, género, especie y subespecie de cada caso del arte. (Yo mismo me pongo el saco.) Gran publicación de Horacio Warpola, Hw Hw Hw. [5 de febrero de 2020.]


jueves, 13 de febrero de 2020

¿Por qué no nos abrimos al arte contemporáneo?

Lo triste son varias cosas:

- que haya tan pobre educación artística en el país (decía Juan Acha: popularizar el arte no sólo es trasladarlo físicamente adonde la gente lo verá, sino sobre todo hacer accesible la educación artística);

- que, a pesar de no saber de un tema, opinemos tajantemente, y que condenemos o celebremos sin tener información (este saco, como varios otros, me queda perfecto);

- que haya quienes podamos tener mucha información pero pobre reflexión, de modo que los datos nos resultan poco útiles;

- que haya quienes juzguen "elitista" y "excluyente" que exista gente especializada (o como se diga) en ciertos temas, como la estética y la teoría del arte, cuando en realidad a la mayoría de especialistas les ha costado gran esfuerzo obtener ese conocimiento, generalmente en condiciones económicas muy precarias (y ese conocimiento es democráticamente accesible a cualquiera que quiera sentarse a estudiarlo);

- que juzguemos por encima del hombro la ignorancia de los demás, cuando en realidad no es tan diferente de la ignorancia propia (y me pongo también este saco);

- que haya quienes medren en este ambiente, a sabiendas de aprovecharse de la confusión;

- que nos quedemos en los escándalos mediáticos pero no en las raíces de los malentendidos y las brechas abismales entre los diferentes "paradigmas" (Kuhn) o "narrativas" (Lyotard-Danto) sobre el arte;

- que no intentemos subsanar un poco el abismo entre un grupo de 'connoisseurs' y una parte grande del público;

- que esos mismos 'connoisseurs' sean re ignorantes acerca de amplísimos aspectos de las vidas de muchas sociedades (más allá de las de Europa y EEUU, o de los grupos hegemónicos de nuestros países pobres);

- que no haya condiciones felices para subsanar los problemas mencionados.

Etcétera.

En ese caldo de cultivo es normal que pululen ideas rancias y absurdas, como la de que cierto arte es "degenerado" (para retomar el término extremo de los nazis) por no basarse en las reglas de las academias artísticas europeas de hace 130 o 200 años.

¿Hay arte contemporáneo muy bobo? Sí, mucho, como igualmente hay pintura figurativa tonta, repetitiva, derivativa, filistea, banal. ¿Hay especulación financiera en el arte contemporáneo? Sí, pero la hay más en la pintura anterior al siglo XIX. (Sumemos que la mayoría de los artistas contemporáneos viven en la precariedad; no todos son Damien Hirst.) Habrá que distinguir entre lo que vale la pena de cada vertiente.

Deberíamos estar más abiertas al diálogo las personas que querríamos que gozar de un Rembrandt no impida reconocer la importancia de Joseph Beuys o John Cage. Creo que de esa apertura depende un poquito del alcance del arte contemporáneo. Habrá que acopiar paciencia y saber argumentar con mayor claridad; se puede y se debe.

Nos toparemos con quienes no se abran a aceptar a su interlocutor, como hay fanáticos de políticos o de equipos deportivos; el diálogo será imposible con ellos y no deberemos insistir en "evangelizarlos" porque nada hay más triste y estéril que la voz del que clama en el desierto.

Y todos tendremos que ponernos a leer mucho.

[11-13 de febrero, 2020.]